The logic of all this nagging at value is the
unavoidable proof that all poetic value is contingent, and ultimately
subjective.
What constituted good poetry for the Anglo
Saxon Scop didn’t pass muster for the Middle English makar, and Wyatt’s courtly
lyric was not Spenser’s ground for either the Fairy Queen or the Shepherd’s Calendar. Coleridge and Wordsworth
rebelled against their past, as did Pound and Eliot for whom Coleridge and
Wordsworth were the past, and their standards of excellence in turn were rejected
or replaced or adapted by others.
The major difference between ‘now’ and ‘then’,
is that while the Scop could be fairly sure that everyone shared an idea of
what a good ‘poem’ was supposed to sound like, since the end of the 19th
century definitions of what constitute a good poem have proliferated to the
point we’re at today where there are so many fragmented versions. No one should
make the mistake of thinking that in music the same standards of excellence
apply to all forms of the art. No one should assume the virtuoso on the concert
platform and the kid in the garage band trashing three chords on an out of tune
guitar should be judged by the same criteria. But we do it all the time in poetry, talking
as though it were homogenous. As if all poems were similar and all poets had
similar aims and ambitions.
When
Coker trashed Keats in the Quarterly Review, underwriting the attack was that by the generally accepted definitions of the
time, Endymion was not a good poem. The grounds of the judgment are there, in
the judgment. Today there are so many different versions of what a good poem is
that one writer’s idea of drivel is another’s award winning entry.
Doesn’t change the fact those definitions
are contingent. (OED uses 2,4,6,7)
Anyone who doesn’t want to accept this is
either willful or ignorant, or willfully ignorant. Anyone trying to argue that there is some
Platonic eternal aesthetic standard of truth or beauty or ‘Poetry” which exists outside of time and language might as well believe all poets are beta androids
from the Planet Zorg: though the latter
would be a much more interesting argument.
However, for a reader, none of this matters. I enjoy The Shooting of
Dan Mcgrew as much as I enjoy The Waste Land, or Briggflatts or the OE Wulf and
Eadwacer. I like a great many of Kipling’s poems and if you don’t, I really
couldn’t care. I suspect Graves was
right, these poems appeal to me for private reasons. I just cannot like Auden’s
poetry: I suspect that says more about me than it does about them.
As honest subjective response there is no
problem with a reader saying “I think Briggflatts is great” it says more about
/I/ than the poem. The problem comes when the critic steps from “I think
Briggflatts is great” to “Briggflatts is (or is not) a great poem”.
One of the ways literary discourse side-stepped
this problem was to substitute ideological scrutiny for any kind of discussion
of artistic value. Admittedly this makes a certain type of literary scholar
feel good about himself /herself and side steps the equally difficult question:
Why are you doing this? Identifying hetero normative discourse in 19th Century poems, or the presence of 17th
Century standards in 17th Century poems passes as a meaningful
activity in some circles.
But what happens to the person interested
in Poetry as an art form who wants to ask or discuss: Is this made thing well
made? Criticism is always “equal to, better than, less than”. But the question
is equal to, better than, less than WHAT? And on which grounds?
I think
the only honest way to go is to establish one’s own examples of excellence, and
be able to verbalise what is excellent about them. In which case the
conversation avoids Graves’ psychological function, and there is the honesty
of “I think this is a good poem because
it meets my standards of ‘good’ which
are ….”
This would avoid so many pointless, heated arguments,
the participants could see at the start that since their definitions of
excellence do not match, it’s unlikely that they are ever going to agree about
anything, and they can spend the time they would have wasted arguing reading
the poems they like.
No comments:
Post a Comment